Articles
Orienting
Our Lives:
The
Importance
of a Liberal Education for Pentecostals in the
Twenty
First
Century1
Michael Palmer
Not long
ago, C-SPAN2’s Book
T.V. channel broadcast a discussion of a new translation of Homer’s
Odyssey.
Four
scholars, including
the transla- tor, talked with each
other and
responded
to callers. One
caller,
who identi- fied herself as a “tongues-talking” Christian from
Mississippi, groused
that too much time and
money
is wasted
perpetuating
the Greek and Latin clas- sics,
whereas more
pressing
issues are evident all around us. The scholars responded briefly,
but their remarks were
fragmentary,
hinted of condescen- sion,
and
generally
failed to discern the caller’s
underlying
concern about what is worthy of human endeavor. It would be convenient for all of us if the caller
happened
to be a hypocrite, a person
incapable
of comprehending an answer,
or simply a kook. For in that event we could
easily justify
dismiss- ing
her out of hand. But she was none of these
things
and, in truth, she speaks
for
many
Pentecostals. Her concern
may
be framed as a
question: Why
do texts and subjects that have no readily discernible
application
to the church or to issues of contemporary life continue to receive attention
among intellectuals and in institutions of
higher
education? More
generally,
the question
is whether the processes and assumptions that underlie the study of these texts and
subjects-processes
and assumptions
traditionally
subsumed under the label ‘liberal education’-have
any prospect
of playing a decisive role in the lives of Pentecostals as they cross the threshold into the twenty- first
century.
I intend to answer this
question affirmatively.
Salient Features
of Liberal Education
Precisely demarcating
the essential features of a liberal
(or liberating)
education is not an inconsiderable
task, partly
because of the various intel- lectual
endeavors,
forms of
training,
and
programs
of
preparation
with .
1 An earlier version of this essay was presented on March 9, 2001, as a plenary address at the 30th annual meeting of the Society for Pentecostal Theology in Tulsa, Oklahoma.
197
1
which it is often confused, and
partly
because the theme itself is elusive. Thus,
to be educated
liberally
is not identical to engaging in scholarship. The former has more to do with a
process
someone
might undergo;
the latter identifies a certain kind of intellectual
activity engaged
in by learned
people. Liberal education also bears no essential connection with the
array
of pro- fessional and vocational
programs-education, marketing, journalism,
and computer science,
to name
only
a few-that have
proliferated
in colleges and universities
during
recent decades. Professional and vocational
pro- grams exemplify
what John
Henry
Newman called the usefiil
(or instrumen- tal) arts, regimens
of
study designed
to impart specific skills and forms of knowledge applicable
to certain roles or career
paths.2
Liberal
education, by contrast,
has less to do with
preparation
for
specific
roles or careers than with
developing
certain
capacities,
not the least of which are those
necessary for
self-understanding
and for
assuming responsibility
within the
larger community.3
Newman himself described it this
way:
“This
process
of train- ing, by
which the intellect, instead of
being
formed or sacrificed to some particular
or accidental
purpose,
some
specific
trade or profession, or study or science, is disciplined for its own sake, for the perception of its own
prop- er object, and for its own
highest culture,
is called Liberal Education.”4
It is a well-known fact that what we today call liberal arts educational institutions
originated
in
Europe during
the
High
Middle
Ages,
and that what we call the liberal arts referred then to two
groups
of academic disci- plines,
one of three
arts,
another of four arts. The threefold
group (which medieval writers called the
trivium)
were communication arts:
grammar, rhetoric,
and
logic.
The fourfold division
(the quadrivium)
consisted of “mathematical” or, as we would describe them,
nonliterary
arts:
geometry,
2 John Henry Newman, The Idea of a U>7iversity (Notre Dame, IN.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982), Discourse VII, “Knowledge Viewed in Relation to Professional Skill,” I 14-135. 3 For an illuminating treatment of this line of reasoning, see Henry G. Bugbee, Jr., “Education and the Style of our Lives,” Profiles 6:4, University of Montana (May 1974), 4-5. Arthur Holmes makes a similar point: “Liberal learning therefore takes the long-range view and con- centrates on what shapes a person’s understanding and values rather than on what he can use in one or two of the roles he might later play.” The Idea of a Christian College, rev. ed. (Grand Rapids, MI.: William changing
B. Eerdmans, 1975), 29.
4 Newman, Idea of a University,115. To those who insist that liberal education must have some instrumental value, Newman offered this
reply:
“If then a
practical
end must be
assigned
to a University course, I say it is that of training good members of society. Its art is the art of social life, and its end is fitness for the world. It neither confines its view to particular professions on the one hand, nor creates heroes or inspires genius on the other” ( 134).
198
2
arithmetic, music,
and
astronomy.5
But this
specific
curriculum was
aug- mented almost from the outset. The
empirical
sciences
(in
their formative stages)
and
theology provided
the
subject
matter for rational
inquiry
in the High
Middle
Ages.
The Renaissance saw the curriculum broadened to include the
study
of classical
languages (Greek
and
Latin)
and classical lit- erature
(drama, poetry, philosophy). By the beginning
of the twentieth cen- tury
the curriculum
ranged
across a broad
spectrum
of disciplines from the humanities to the natural and social sciences.
Today,
a
century later,
it is more cross
disciplinary
and cross cultural than ever before. The historical trend to expand and revise the liberal arts does not prove that the curriculum is altogether
arbitrary. (Certain
texts and materials do in fact lend themselves more
readily, fully,
and
enduringly
to the educative
process.)
But it does show that the curriculum itself, the specific subject
matter,
if you will, does not essentially define liberal education.
As a first
approximation
to providing a positive account of liberal edu- cation,
I take
my cue from Newman’s description
cited earlier: He spoke of a process of
training, by
which the intellect is disciplined for its own sake and for the
perception
of its own
proper object.
What are the essential fea- tures of an educative
process
that thus disciplines the intellect?
To
begin
with, liberal education involves
awakening
to the
living sig- nificance of the
seemingly
dead
past.6
The
general
semanticist Alfred
5 Although the seven liberal arts (composed of the trivium and guadrivium) formed the core of university education in the High Middle Ages, the specific groupings originated much earli- er with Martianus Capella, a fourth-century contemporary of and a fellow North African. Martianus introduced the seven arts (and the distinctive threefold-fourfold Augustine
in a treatise with the curious
groupings)
title, The Marriage of Philology and Mercury. By the time he ulated his
stip-
specific curriculum, Christians were already studying grammar, rhetoric, and classi- cal
literature, following the Roman and curriculum. The practice was controversial: Tertullian
objected strenuously
to the system
adoption of classical culture. But others, including Jerome, Ambrose, and Augustine, saw value in classical culture and classical education. Augustine,
who was highly critical of some of the classical tradition, Christians to adopt the Roman system of education and the use of aspects classical literature for urged pragmatic rea- sons : to maintain a literate church. To that end he advocated the preparation of compendia of the liberal arts, which took the form of summaries of those aspects of classical philosophy and literature deemed to be consistent with Christian doctrine. For a fuller treatment of these and
related issues, see Norman F. Cantor, The Civilization of the Middle Ages (New York: Harper Collins, 1993), 66, 67, 80-84. Also see Arthur F. Holmes, Building The Christian Academy (Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 2001 ).
6 What I here call awakening to the past has certain affinities with Gabriel Marcel’s use of the term “recollection.” See “On the
trans.
Ontological Mystery,” in The Philosophy of Existentialism,
Manya Harari (New York: Citadel Press, 1956; reprint, Carol Publishing Group, 1995), 9-46, esp. 23-25. Also, see Marcel’s treatment of the French word reconnaissance and its cog- nate reconnaitre in “Philosophy As I See It,” in The Owl of Minerva:
199
3
deliberate
judgment.
To say, therefore, that liberal education entails
tutelage in choice means that liberal education has to do
fundamentally
with devel- oping
in individuals the capacity for deliberate judgment.9
But the exercise of deliberate
judgment
can
hardly
be realized
apart from
enlivening
the
imagination.
Practical
people-people disposed
to action directed toward immediate or
tangible
results-sometimes criticize liberal
learning
on the grounds that it yields no definite answers. In a certain narrow sense the criticism is accurate. The caller who asked the scholars on C-SPAN2’s Book T.V,
“Why,
in the face of so
many pressing issues,
we should continue to
study
classical literature?” made a valid
assumption. Studying
Homer’s
Odyssey
is unlikely to have a direct
bearing
on even a sin- gle important contemporary
social issue. In that sense-and here is the crit- icism-it is useless. The same can be said for the
study
of
any particular piece
of literature, drama,
philosophy, poetry,
or history. But the assumption on which the criticism rests
quite
misses the
larger point. Studying
these works does not aim to provide specific solutions to
practical problems.
On the contrary, it aims to enliven the imagination, and this means that the chief value of studying them lies with their
capacity
to provoke thought and pres- ent familiar
things
in unfamiliar
ways.10
Bertrand Russell made this
point when he said that the value of philosophy lies less in its
ability
to provide definite answers than in the
uncertainty
it engenders:
The man who has no tincture of philosophy goes through life in the prejudices derived from common sense, from the habitual beliefs imprisoned of his age or nation, and from convictions which have
grown up
in his mind without the cooperation or consent of his deliberate reason…
unable to tell us with certainty what is the true answer to the doubts which it raises, is able to suggest many possibilities which Philosophy though
enlarge our thoughts and free them from the tyranny of custom.l I
Russell’s
point
about
philosophy
holds
equally
for literature,
poetry, history, and
any
of the other
subjects
of inquiry ordinarily associated with the liber- al arts.
They
all enliven the imagination and thereby militate
against
various
9 See my “Elements of a Christian Worldview,” in Elements of a Christian Worldview, ed. and comp.
Michael D. Palmer (Springfield, MS: Logion Press, 1998), 19-78, esp. 24-27. 10 Edward De Bono uses the expression “lateral thinking” to describe the
in unfamiliar “Lateral he “seeks
process of looking at familiar things
ways. thinking,” says,
to get away from the
pat- terns that are leading one in a definite direction and to move sideways by reforming the
pat- terns.” New Think (New York: Avon, 1971 ), 15.
11 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1969), 156, 157.
201
4
Korzybski
once described humankind as “a time-binding class of life His description
evokes an intriguing image of what it means to live humanly. We do not so much build
upon
the
past
as gather it together and pull it forward to our own
time;
we do not so much stand on the shoulders of our predeces- sors as assimilate their contributions and treat them as if they were our own. Korzybski
does not
say so,
but
surely
much of this
time-binding activity, perhaps
most of it, is unintentional. It goes on day in and
day out,
but the individual for the most
part does not notice (much
less comprehend) what is being
thus
gathered
and bound
together
to make a self. Liberal education explicitly
turns attention to the
time-binding process
and
explores
the tem- poral
strands from our cultural and intellectual
heritage
that we have unwit- tingly gathered together
to form ourselves.
Through
the
study
of the
past- whether in the works of philosophers, church fathers,
poets, playwrights,
or novelists-liberal education
helps
us remember who we are.
Liberal education is also tutelage in choice. This becomes evident if we consider the
way people commonly acquire
the core beliefs and
practices that
comprise
their worldview.
Children,
for instance, receive their world- view
uncritically
as an inheritance. Their core
beliefs, priorities,
and ideals show
up
in their
speech, actions,
and social
arrangements,
but
they
lack appreciation
of either their
origins
or implications. Possessing them in this sense
(uncritically,
as an inheritance) is not
yet
to have chosen them and is thus not
yet
to own them
fully.
Mature
ownership requires
the exercise of choice. But
choosing,
in the
respect
intended
here,
does not mean
merely that one selects one set of beliefs,
priorities,
and ideals from
among
several available
options,
as if picking a box of breakfast cereal from the shelf at the supermarket.
It refers rather to a circumspect style of life characterized
by alertness, careful and thorough consideration of alternatives, appreciation
of logical
commitments,
and awareness of consequences. Such a style of life cannot
guarantee uniformly good
results, but it does minimize
the likelihood that one will fall prey to the whims of other
people
or succumb to the con- tingencies
of natural forces. As one author has pointed out, “We may not be the captains of our fate and the masters of our soul with total
ability
to con- trol the environment around us, but we are the captains of our fate and mas- ters of our soul in our
ability
to be deliberative about the life we lead…”8 Quite simply, choosing,
in the sense intended
here, involves
the exercise of
Philosophers on Philosophy, ed. Charles J. Bontempo and S. Jack Odell (New York: McGraw Hill
Paperbacks, 1975), 119-122.
‘
7 Alfred Korzybski, Science and Sanity (Lakeville, CN: International Non-Aristotelian Library, 1933), “Preliminaries,” 1:7-18; “Introduction,” 3:38-52.
8 Vincent E. Rush, The Responsible Christian (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1984), 94.
200
5
forms of dogmatism, prejudice masquerading as common
sense,
and cultur- al bias.
Enlivening
the
imagination
has much to do with
learning
to appreciate questions, by
which I mean
learning
to attend to them
carefully,
not for a brief time but
patiently
and
searchingly
over the
long
haul. In this connec- tion,
I am reminded of Rainer Maria Rilke’s
response
to a young aspiring poet
who once
sought
his advice on several
issues,
especially
ones about his poetic ability
and his own unmade future:
You are so young, so before all beginning, and I want to beg you, as much as I can, dear sir, to be patient toward all that is unsolved in heart and to
your
try to love the questions themselves like locked rooms and like books that are written in a
very foreign tongue. Do not now seek the answers, which cannot be given you because you would not be able to live them. And the point is, to live everything. Live the questions now. Perhaps you
will then gradually, without
2
noticing it, live along some dis- tant day into the answers.l2
Rilke’s recommendation to live the questions represents an invitation to adopt
an
essentially
reflective
posture
toward life.l3 We
reflect
when we attentively
attend to the ways and extent to which we are implicated in what we
study
or experience, when we consider what
something
means to us, or when we
weigh
the moral claim that
something
or someone has on us.l4 Much
(perhaps most)
of our
thought
is analytical and calculative.
Analysis and calculation make
ordinary
life
possible
because
they
aim at
solving problems.
Their
goal
is to
provide specific
answers to
specific questions. The
products
of analysis and calculation are things like structural
drawings, digital devices,
business
plans,
deductive
logic proofs,
and solutions to chess problems. By contrast,
reflective
thinking
is more like
waiting, taking
time to let
questions deepen by affording
them
patient
consideration. Reflection is less an abandonment of answers than
preparation
of the self to receive answers in due time. It is also
preparation
to understand that some of the answers central to our well-being can never be grasped definitively, but must
12 Rainer Maria Rilke, Letters to a Young Poet, rev. ed., trans. M. D. Herter Norton (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1934, 1962), 34, 35.
13 For a particularly engaging example of reflective thinking, see Henry G.
Inward A in Journal Form
Bugbee, Jr., The
Morning, Philosophical Exploration (State College, PA: Bald Eagle Press, 1958; reprint, Harper and Row, 1976; reprint with an introduction by Edward F.
of
Mooney, University Georgia Press, 1999).
14 The expression “retlective thought” comes close to Martin Heidegger’s use of the expres- sion “meditative thinking.” See Discourse on Thinking, trans. John M. Anderson and E. Hans Freund (New York: Harper & Row, 1966), 46.
202
6
always
and
necessarily
remain
partial
and tentative.
Reflection,
even when it yields no conclusive answers, liberates us from naive
optimism
and
petty fear as well as from the
misconceptions
that
everything
must
go
our
way and that no one else’s interests are as important as our own.
A
Theological Argument
.
To this point I have described what I believe to be the essential features of liberal education, education characterized not so much
by its specific
cur- riculum as
by
the
types
of
thinking
and
responding
it
attempts
to foster. These features include
developing
an historical
sensibility, learning
to choose
(deliberately
and circumspectly),
learning
to think
imaginatively
and with
appreciation
for questions, and
adopting
a reflective
posture.
This
list, though
not exclusive, does
identify
some of the most
important
features of an education that can liberate us from the provinciality of immediate
expe- rience,
enhance our
resourcefulness,
and
deepen
our
capacity
to assume responsibility
for
meaning.
For
some,
the
foregoing
discussion
provides ample
evidence in itself, without further elaboration, of the value of liberal education.
Understanding its processes and aims constitutes sufficient
grounds
to establish its validity and
importance.
Whenever I am tempted
by this line of reasoning,
I think of people
like the Book T.V. caller, and countless others whom I have known over the
years
in various Pentecostal
congregations,
for whom the value of liberal education is far from evident. Their
skepticism typically
draws on several
sources, including
broad cultural
trends,
such as the
pragmatism
and can-do-ism so common
among Americans; long-standing
and
deep-seated anti-intellectualism;
and
simplistic
and narrow views about the
activity
of the
Holy Spirit
and the role of the Bible in the life of believers. In the remainder of this
paper
I address these concerns with two kinds of
argu- ments : one theological, the other
practical.
I begin with the
theological argu- ment.
Among Pentecostals, developing appreciation
for liberal education is difficult for the reasons
just
now cited but also because it does not seem to integrate obviously
with the
theological principles
that have
historically driven Pentecostalism. Like most other branches of
Christianity, Pentecostalism has claimed to take the entire canon
seriously.
But also like most other branches of
Christianity,
it has emphasized some
passages
more than others.
Functionally
it has
developed
a canon within the canon. For instance,
Acts 2 figures prominently within the Pentecostal canon, as do cer- tain
prophetic
and eschatological texts. As a movement devoted to the work of missions, Pentecostalism has also made Matthew 28:18-20, the so-called
203
7
great commission,
a central text in its canon. 15 In
fact,
this text has
played such a prominent motivational and
theological
role in Pentecostalism
(and has been
interpreted
in such a narrow
way)
as to create the
misleading impression
that humankind’s most fundamental call is to engage in evange- lization. The
practical upshot
of this
misconception
is both
good
and bad. Pentecostalism has become a
leading
force in missions
work,
and Pentecostal churches worldwide have
grown spectacularly during
the twen- tieth century; but education has
generally suffered, being
reduced to the role of vocational
training
for missions or parish work. Pentecostals have
rightly reminded the Christian world that authentic
worship
has an affective com- ponent ;
but
they
have
largely
banished the intellect from their
conception and
practice
of
worship.
The
emphasis
on missions and
evangelism
has brought dignity
and
prestige
to ecclesiastical
callings;
but it has demeaned all other
callings by relegating
them to second-class status.
Without in any way denigrating the work of evangelism, we must insist that our most basic call lies elsewhere. It is best understood
by reference to the Genesis creation account: that we were created in God’s own
image (Genesis 1:26, 27).
The
Scriptures
seem to imply two
primary purposes
for being
created in God’s
image.
The first concerns communion with God. That we have been formed in God’s
image (something
not claimed for any of the other
creatures) suggests
a certain
affinity
and
mutuality
between God and humankind: We are not God’s
equal,
but we were created to be God’s vis-a- vis. The Westminster Catechism
acknowledges
this
purpose
when it
pro- claims that “Man’s chief end is to glorify God and to
enjoy
him forever.” Everything
else is subordinate to this
purpose.
The work of missions and evangelism, though urgent,
is related to this ultimate
purpose only
indirect- ly, due to humankind’s estrangement
from God. When
explicit proclamation of the gospel is successful, it places men and women in a position to realize their ultimate
calling:
communion with their Creator.
In the
history
of Pentecostalism, the so-called
“great
commission” in Matthew 28-“Go therefore and make
disciples
of all nations”-has been read
narrowly
as a commandment to undertake the work of evangelism. But it need not be read
narrowly. Making disciples
can
perfectly
well be under- stood as a mandate to tutor
people
toward a full
understanding
of their
pri- mary calling
before God and to assist them in freely responding to that call. If so understood, then whatever else this
tutelage entails, surely
it must include
restoring, developing,
and
disciplining
the full
range
of God-given
15 Matthew 25:31-46, the judgment of the nations, has been notably absent from the Pentecostal canon, though there is some recent evidence that this is beginning to change.
204
8
potentialities
associated with the life of the mind-such as those elaborated earlier.
The second
purpose
of creation concerns secular
things:
It calls for human
beings
to undertake a range of endeavors summarized in the
expres- sion “dominion”
(Genesis 1; Psalms 8; Hebrews 2). Broadly speaking,
these endeavors are cultural activities
(leading
some to speak of a cultural man- date to
manage
our own and nature’s resources
creatively
and
wisely).lt’ They
include
everything
from
attending
to nature
(as
in
naming
creatures and
having
dominion over
them 17) to making
artifacts.1
g
But here it is important to exercise care in describing both the
purpose and the activities that
exemplify
it. In the divine scheme of things, culture- making
is not fundamentally different from
communing
with God. In other words, we quite miss the point
if we
suggest
that in the first instance God calls us to communion and then later directs us to leave the divine,
holy pres- ence and
dirty
our hands
by engaging
in culture-making.
Rather,
culture- making
articulates
specific ways
of preparing
for, entering into, and express- ing
communion.
By taking
the cultural mandate
seriously
we give concrete expression
to our
relationship
with the Creator in whose
image
we are made.19
9
From this vantage
point,
the connection with liberal education is not dif- ficult to see. Even in its most humble
elements-learning
to read, to write, to listen, to perceive sensitively and
noticingly,
to entertain
possibilities,
and to draw inferences-liberal education is preparation for answering
responsi- bly
to tht cultural mandate in all of our
creaturely
activities. More
general-
16 See Holmes, The Idea of a Christian College, 19. In addition to a mandate to create culture, Miroslav Volf sees in Scripture a mandate to with God in transforming culture. “Work,” in Elements of a Christian Worldview, ed. cooperate Palmer, 219-239, especially 228, 229. 17 For a fuller discussion of the way in which naming is a culture-making activity that evidence of how human beings are made in the image of God, see Twila Brown
gives
Edwards, “The Place of Literature in a Christian Worldview,” in Elements of a Christian Worldview, ed. Palmer, 339-375, “Creation,” 341-348. Additional notable sources include: Michael Edwards, Towards a Christian Poetics (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 1984); J.R.R. Tolkiett, “On Fairy Tales,” in The Tolkien Reader (New York: Ballantine Press, 1966); and Madeleine L’Engle, Walking
on Water: Reflections on Faith and Art (Wheaton, IL: Harold Shaw, 1980).
18 The writer of Exodus singles out two artisans, Bezalel and Oholiab, for special comment. Of Bezalel we are told, “See, I [the Lord] have called
with divine with and
by name Bezalel …
and I have filled him
spirit, ability, intelligence,
in kind of craft, to devise artistic designs, to work in and
knowledge every
gold, silver, bronze, in cutting stones for setting, and in carving wood, in every kind of craft” (Exodus 31:1-5).
19 As Arthur Holmes has said, “While all nature declares the glory of God, we human beings uniquely image the Creator in our created creativity.” The Idea of a Christian College. 21.
205
9
ly, within the framework of a Christian
worldview,
liberal education must be understood as developing our
capacity
to image God in the fullness of our humanity,
which is our
highest
call.
Practical Considerations
If the
preceding theological argument
is
cogent,
it
applies
to all Christians, without regard
to denominational affiliation or historical
place- ment. In the final section of this
paper,
I turn to some
practical
considera- tions with the aim of
demonstrating
how liberal education can assist Pentecostals in facets of life that matter, or ought to matter,
deeply
to them. But before
launching
into the substance of the
arguments,
I wish to clarify precisely
the nature of my thesis. I am not
saying that,
after a century
(more or less) of missionary endeavor, church
planting,
and instruction in doctrine, Pentecostals are now
sufficiently
mature
spiritually
to cope with the tempta- tions
posed by the arts,
sciences,
and humanities. Nor am I saying that, after decades of
freeing
themselves from the lowest socioeconomic stratum, Pentecostals have now earned the right to indulge themselves in some edu- cational luxuries. Liberal education is neither a temptation that
only
mature Christians can be trusted with, nor a fringe benefit for upwardly mobile
peo- ple who have
“arrived.” In my view, Pentecostals
currently
find themselves at an historical
turning point
that is at once
hopeful
and
precarious-hope- ful,
because
demographics
and wider
acceptance by
the dominant culture have
placed
them in a strategic position both to challenge and to shape the surrounding
culture:
precarious,
because for too
long they
have traded on the experiential aspects of faith and sold short the life of the mind.
The
precariousness
of Pentecostals shows itself in two
general ways. First, although they
have
long
criticized
negative
trends in the
surrounding culture,
their lack of a robust intellectual tradition has left them vulnerable to
being coopted by
the
very
trends
they
claim to disdain. For
instance, Pentecostals (like
evangelicals)
have created and embraced “Christian”
pop music that is little different from American
pop music,
with secular musi- cians
leading
the way and calling the tune. Second, Pentecostals’ tradition of anti-intellectualism has left them with
only
scant resources for
dealing
with new cultural and intellectual issues.
They
have
yet
to learn that to combat the
opponent
one must
thoroughly
understand him. So
my
thesis about the importance
of liberal education has nothing to do with Pentecostals
availing themselves of
“interesting”
or “nice” educational electives from time to time-as if to say,
reading
Homer’s
Odyssey
is OK after
all,
so
long
as it does not distract from the really important tasks at hand. In the last analysis, whether Pentecostals come to value liberal education is a matter of immense practical consequence
and considerable
urgency,
because how
they finally
206
10
come to live their lives will depend in large measure on the stewardship
they exercise
over the processes that shape their minds.
I see two
significant
areas in which liberal education can have a salu- tary
effect on Pentecostals:
(1) appropriating
the
past
in an active and searching manner; (2) deepening
and informing moral consciousness. In the remainder of this
essay,
I speak to each of these
briefly.
Appropriating
the Past
To say that Pentecostals lack historical
perspective
is only partly true. Several Pentecostal denominations and some universities have
developed archives. Furthermore, never before in the
history
of Pentecostalism have there been more or better Pentecostal
historians,
not to mention several out- standing
scholars of Pentecostal
history
who do not themselves claim to be Pentecostal. In addition, the vast majority of Pentecostal institutions of high- er education offer courses on the
history
of the modem Pentecostal move- ment. With few exceptions
however,
these sources of Pentecostal
history
are having
little discernible
impact
on the thousands of Pentecostal churches around the world. Yet it is primarily at this
level,
the local church, that his- torical
perspective
is at one and the same time most
evidently languishing and
yet
most
urgently
needed. Sometimes with
good intention,
and some- times
seemingly
with no intention at all, Pentecostal churches have
adopted “contemporary”
forms of
congregational worship. Hymns,
which maintain minimal connection to the
past,
are
commonly
set aside in favor of contem- porary worship songs.
In the
attempt
to
keep pace
with the
popular youth culture, some churches have
relegated adults, particularly
the oldest ones, to the sidelines. Even where this has not occurred,
congregations
are often
seg- regated according
to age and
interest,
with the effect that children and teens have little or no contact with the older
members, who
are the bearers of tra- dition and who
provide
a critical link to the
past. Also, many
Pentecostal churches, following
the seeker
model, have banished
all Christian
symbol- ism from their
places
of
worship.20
Since Pentecostal churches
generally lean
strongly
toward the non-
liturgical
side of Christian tradition
anyway, and thus have few community rituals to connect them to the past, the loss of any residual symbolism
does not bode well for nurturing
appreciation
for the past. Finally, Pentecostals,
like their
contemporaries in the rest of the
cul-
20 Pentecostal churches have also followed the lead of other churches in down-playing, or even
their ties to denominations. In the words of Robert Wuthnow, “Growing numbers of churches might be characterized as open systems, attempting to embrace everyone, while abandoning,
to impose little on anyone.” Christianity in the Twenty-first Century: Reflections on the Challenges Ahead (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 49.
attempting
207
11
ture, struggle
with transition. For various
reasons,
families relocate with increasing frequency
and so lose whatever connection
they may
have had with their former
place
of
worship
and
commonly
have no
opportunity
or reason to delve
deeply
into the traditions and defining practices of their new church.
Of course, none of these
phenomena,
taken
singly,
leads
inevitably
to loss of meaningful connection to the past. But in sum
they paint
a picture of churches that, at best,
ignore
their
history.
But
why
is this a problem, and what
might
liberal education do to ameliorate the situation?
Quite simply, the answer to the first
question
is that churches are communities. If they are to be genuine,
sustaining
communities in the midst of an otherwise individ- ualistic nation,
they
must have a robust
conception
of the past. To borrow an expression
from Robert Bellah and his
colleagues,
churches must be com- munities
of memory,
communities that do not
forget
the
past
because
they actively engage
in
telling
and
retelling
their central
story.21 This story,
or collective
history (what
Bellah calls a “constitutive
narrative”),
is not a detached recitation of dates and events but a
living
tradition that offers examples
of men and women who have embodied and
exemplified
the meaning
of the
community.
In Bellah’s
view,
communities of
memory
are essential to the formation of an individual’s
identity, precisely
because
they provide
individuals a collective
history,
a tradition. Alasdair
Maclntyre puts the matter this
way:
A living tradition … is an historically extended, socially embodied argu- ment, and an argument precisely in part about the goods which constitute that tradition. Within a tradition the pursuit of goods extends
sometimes
through generations, through many generations. Hence the individ- ual’s search for his or her
good is generally and characteristically con- ducted within a context defined
by those traditions of which the individ- ual’s life is a part.22
.
If a church’s collective
history
is weak or
ignored-in short,
if a church defaults on its role as a community of memory-then the people whose lives are interwoven with that church are also
likely
to have a weak or passive sense of their own
identity
as Christians. As Robert Wuthnow has observed, “While the idea of
church-as-storyteller may
seem to diminish its
impor-
21 Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swindler, and Steven M. Tipton,
Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1985), 152-157.
22 Alasdair Maclntyre, After Virtue : A Study in Moral Theorv, 2d ed. (Notre Dame, IN: University
of Notre Dame Press, 1987), 222.
208
12
tance,
this function must
actually
be seen as having the utmost
significance. For the
very
likelihood of
anyone
in the future
retaining
the
identity
of ‘Christian’
depends
on it.”23
If the
preceding analysis
is correct,
reinvigorating
a sense of historical placement
is a matter of considerable
significance
for Pentecostal churches. But
addressing
the current situation will take more than
simply pointing
out the loss of tradition. For Pentecostal churches to become
genuine
and sus- taining
communities of memory will
require precisely
the kinds of intellec- tual commitments identified earlier as defining features of a liberally edu- cated mind.
Congregations
and their leaders must look not
only prospec- tively,
but also
retrospectively,
which is to say the past must be made a mat- ter of conversation. But to be successful over the
long haul,
this conversa- tion cannot be entered into
haphazardly
or
intermittently.
It must be initiat- ed as a matter of genuine choice
(deliberately), approached
in the vein of asking
what the past can mean for the
present (reflectively),
and undertaken in a purposeful, sustained, and concerted
way.
Informing
Moral Consciousness
In order to establish a framework for
talking meaningfully
about informing
the moral consciousness of Pentecostals, I begin with a point of comparison.24
In the Catholic
tradition,
Thomas
Aquinas’s
treatment of nat- ural law comes
quickly
to mind as
exemplifying
what it means for a Christian tradition to embrace a principled, widely
applicable,
and distinc- tive
approach
to moral issues. Classical Pentecostals have not yet embraced a similarly
compelling
and
clearly
articulated moral
theory.
This fact is less indicative of
outright disagreement among
Pentecostals than it is of the embryonic-or perhaps missinb state
of discussion over moral
theory
in Pentecostal circles. Holiness
Pentecostals,
for
example,
have written at length
about the nature, value, and role of sanctification. But beyond
saying what sanctification
might
mean for one’s outward
appearance,
for
example, conservative dress codes, or personal behavior, such as refraining from con- suming alcohol, smoking, dancing, gambling,
and
going
to
movies, they have
generally
drawn few moral
implications.
On the other hand, Finished
23 Wuthnow, Christianity in the Twenty-first Century, 48. For a fuller discussion of the
of the church as a community of memory, loss of
topic
tradition, and the importance of story telling, see especially chapter 3, “The Place for the Christian,” 42-54.
24 The remarks in this section derive from my essay “Ethics in the Classical Pentecostal Tradition,” in The New International Dictionary of Pentecostal and Charismatic Movements, Revised and Expanded Edition, ed. Stanley M. Burgess, assoc. ed. Ed van der Mass (Grand Rapids,
MI: Zondervan, 2001 ).
209
13
Work
Pentecostals, such as the Assemblies of God, have
generally
down- played
the
importance
of
developing
a comprehensive moral
theory.
As a result,
it is possible to sketch
only
in the most tentative and provisional way the main lines of a Pentecostal moral
theory.
Murray Dempster,
one of
only
a few Pentecostal scholars to
attempt such a sketch, has proposed
general
criteria for a Pentecostal moral
theory.25 In his
view,
an adequate Pentecostal moral
theory
must be theocentric. This means,
in part, that a clear
understanding
of God
(particularly
God’s holi- ness and
goodness)
must
guide
one’s life. But more
importantly,
it means that Pentecostals must
distinguish
themselves from other Christians in their view that God’s
Spirit
resides at the center of all
aspects
of Pentecostal life-including
its social,
political,
and economic
practices
and institutions. In
addition, Dempster believes
that an
adequate
Pentecostal moral
theory ought
to be
distinguished by
its concept of the
Imago Dei,
its
portrayal
of what it means to be a covenant
people,
its prophetic tradition of social criti- cism,
and its concern for the
poor,
the
weak, and the disenfranchised. Elaborating
on a theme first articulated
by Stanley Hauerwas, Dempster
also contends that an adequate Pentecostal moral
theory
should
provide
a place for
imagination.
In his
view, human
imagination
can be an effective instru- ment of God’s
Spirit
to stimulate
redemptive
and transformative action in a fractured and chaotic world.
Within a network of valued relationships and activity, an ethics of
.
ination stimulates the moral agent in response to God’s acts to reenact the imag-
human actions of liberation,
justice,
love and reconciliation
through
a
profound identification with the theological convictions and ethical norms of the biblical stories associated with
God’s creative power. An
ethics of imagination not only aims at the reenactment of its stories, but
also at the embodiment of its stories in the formation of the church as the
new society.26
I shall return later to
Dempster’s
interest in “an ethics of
imagination”
in connection with the role of liberal education in the lives of Pentecostals.
Howard
Kenyon,
another Pentecostal scholar, believes
that, although
it is
appropriate
for Pentecostal ethicists to call attention
(as Dempster
has done)
to the
experience
of
Spirit baptism,
“what is
equally
needed is an
25 Murray Dempster, “Pentecostal Social Concern and the Biblical Mandate of Social Justice,” Pentecostal Theology 9:2 (Fall 1987), 129-153; and “Soundings
in the Moral Significance of Glossolalia,” in Pastoral Problems in the Pentecostal- Charismatic Movement, ed. Harold D. Hunter (Cleveland, TN: Church of God School of Theology, 1983), 1-32.
26 Dempster, “Soundings in the Moral Significance of Glossolalia,” 31.
210
14
understanding
of the significance that the concept ‘Age of the Spirit’ has had on the Pentecostal worldview.”27
What made the early pioneers truly Pentecostal was more than just the ability
to speak a language they had not formally studied. What made them Pentecostal was that their entire orientation was governed by the bold notion that they were living in the Age of the Spirit.28
For
Kenyon,
this broader
emphasis
on the concept ‘Age of the Spirit’ means that an
adequate
Pentecostal moral
theory
must be
eschatological
and prophetic.
To be eschatological is to be future-oriented: “The final
hope
of the believer lies in the blessed
hope,
this hope that Christ will return and that the fulfillment of all promise lies in the age to come.” To be prophetic means to proclaim God’s word
boldly
and to articulate its social
implications
for the
present day,
rather than
simply
to foretell future events.
(His
under- standing
of the
prophetic
role of Pentecostals resembles
Dempster’s
treat- ment of the
prophetic
tradition of social
criticism.) Finally, Kenyon
believes that an adequate Pentecostal moral
theory-eschatological
and
prophetic
at its core-will
embody
three fundamental
themes,
which will
provide
its points
of departure for action: liberation,
reconciliation,
and justice.29
It is
important
to
keep
in mind that the sketches of moral
theory described here are idealizations. At no time during the rise of Pentecostalism have
they (or any other
models for Pentecostal moral
theory)
been
formally discussed and filled out in a comprehensive way (much less adopted)
by the governing body
of any Pentecostal denomination or movement. In a certain respect,
this result is exactly what one would
expect
from a religious move- ment whose
pioneers
were bound
by
a common
experience
rather than a common creed.
But there is reason to believe that the historical
reality
is actually more complex
and
regrettable
than
simply saying
that Pentecostals have not
yet developed
a full-bodied moral
theory. Dempster,
for
instance, implies
that Pentecostalism
has come
perilously
close to what he calls “trivialization” and
“evangelicalization”
of the moral life. The moral life is “trivialized” when Pentecostals diminish its weightiness by focusing narrowly on incon- sequential, personal,
and external behaviors. It is
“evangelicalized”
when they
occlude or reject
altogether
certain
distinctively
Pentecostal beliefs and
27 Howard N. Kenyon, An Analysis of Ethical Issues in the History of the Assemblies of God (Ph. D. diss., Baylor University, 1988), 419. ,
28 Ibid., 414.
29 Ibid., 419, 420.
211
15
practices
and
uncritically
assimilate themselves into the
evangelical
main- stream.3?
Although Dempster
does not
actually say
that Pentecostals have succumbed to these reactions, the historical evidence
strongly suggests
that both have occurred in varying
degrees
in classical Pentecostal
groups.
Kenyon
carries the
critique
farther than
Dempster. Identifying
the Assemblies of God as an example of what can
go wrong
with a Pentecostal movement as it
proceeds through
various
stages
of institutionalization, he argues
that in three areas – the status of African Americans in church mem- bership
and
ministry,
the role of women in ministry, and the participation of Christians in war-the Assemblies of God has
“developed
a set of moral principles lacking
the distinctiveness of a thoroughgoing Pentecostal social ethic.” In its early formative
years, according
to Kenyon, the denomination’s ethical
posture
was
shaped by
four
theological emphases:
the imminent return of Christ, the authority of Scripture, the
present Age
of the
Spirit,
and the
priority
of world
evangelization.
He contends that, of the four,
only two-the
authority
of
Scripture
and the
priority
of world
evangelization- continue to have
significant impact.
In his view, the Assemblies of God has been
“reactionary, portrayed
in the denomination’s
ambiguous
attitude toward blacks;
dogmatic,
demonstrated in the
fellowship’s
mixed
approach to women in ministry; and
pragmatic,
illustrated in the General Council’s dramatic shifts in its attitudes toward
participation
in
Mel Robeck offers an even broader
critique
of the Pentecostal move- ment.32 In his view, Pentecostals have been
quick
to recite the proclamation Jesus made at the
beginning
of his ministry: “The
Spirit
of the Lord is upon me, because
he has anointed me to bring good news to the poor. He has sent me to proclaim release to the
captives
and recovery of sight to the blind, to let the
oppressed go
free,
to
proclaim
the
year
of the Lord’s favor”
(Luke 4:18-19).
But having invoked this
passage
as though they were
empowered to do the same things as Jesus, Pentecostals have
actually appropriated
them
30 Dempster, “Soundings in the Moral Significance of Glossolalia,” 32.
31 Kenyon, An Analysis of Ethical Issues in the History of the Assemblies of God, iii. 32 Cecil M. Robeck, Jr. “Pentecostals and Social Ethics,” Pneumu: The Journal of the Society for
Pentecostal Theology 9:2 (Fall 1987), 103-107. Robeck prefaces his critique with two histor- ical observations: First, revivalism and the Holiness Movement were both
deeply revivalism and to
involved in
about social transformation. Second, Pentecostals are heirs both to
the Holiness bringing Movement: “The spiritual and social commitments of these movements lie behind the birth of Pentecostalism” (103). Robeck believes that there is ample historical evidence of this heritage of commitment to social transformation. He cites a number of examples including A.J. Tomlinson and his ministry to the poor of Appalachia, Lilian Trasher and her orphanage for Egyptian children, Aimee Semple McPherson and her Temple Commissary, and William J. Seymour’s
contribution to racial equality in the church.
212
16
only
in a narrow and limited
way.
Robeck
says,
.
While Pentecostals have ministered freely to those
have often
enduring spiritual poverty, they ignored the plight of the economically of deprived
our society. The approach all too often has been to move away from the city, and away from the and to argue that Jesus anticipated that we would always have the poor,
problem of the poor around….
Pentecostals have typically overlooked those who are captive to the abuses of the unjust
structures of or ideology, and at times have turned their eyes away
from the society
plight of those who are oppressed by their fellow human
beings, whether by economic, political, social, military or even religious
means.33
‘
Robeck believes several factors
explain why Pentecostals departed
from their historical
heritage
of social ethics.
Among
them:
“[T]he
rise of the old liberalism and the social
gospel
tended to taint
Pentecostal, holiness,
and evangelical
involvement with issues of social
justice. [Social activism] became identified as a ‘liberal’
tool,
and therefore as something ‘off limits’ to Pentecostals.” Moreover, “the issue of peer pressure also came into play. As Pentecostals rubbed shoulders with
evangelicals they
also
adopted
the values and concerns of
evangelicals
who stood over
against
‘liberals’ who employed
the social
gospel.”34
Robeck’s
analysis
reinforces the
point
that Pentecostals lack a general and
principled approach
to moral issues. As a result
they
have ended
up responding
to new social
developments
and moral
challenges
in an ad hoc manner,
which in
part explains why
their
history
is scattered with moral lapses
and
compromises.
Of course,
embracing
a general moral
theory
is no guarantee
that similar moral
lapses
and compromises can be avoided in the future. But
surely
Pentecostals have little
prospect
of avoiding them in the absence of such a moral framework. We
may ask,
therefore,
“what it will take to develop a clear and distinctive moral
theory
that is true to the move- ment’s most basic historical and
theological
commitments?”
Asking
this question,
of course, is not the same as asking what such a theory would look like. Rather, it involves
focusing
on the conditions
necessary
for developing a satisfactory theory in the first
place.
And here I wish to focus the discus- sion once
again
on the
importance
of liberal education
by recalling Dempster’s
evocative
expression
“ethics of imagination.”
Dempster implies
that an ethics of
imagination
both reflects on the moral thrust of the Bible’s central narratives and seeks to instantiate the
33 Ibid., 104. 34 Ibid., 106.
213
17
moral
implications
of these narratives in the church.
Unquestionably,
reflect- ing carefully
on the biblical narratives has the potential to enliven the imag- ination. But we must not underestimate the degree to which these narratives are encrusted in a tradition of
interpretation (including
recent Pentecostal tradition)
that militates
against reading
them afresh and
engaging
them in a way
that
truly
offers the
prospect
of refocusing the church’s moral
energy. Moreover, twenty-first century Pentecostals
are no less
susceptible
to dog- matism,
cultural
bias,
and
prejudices masquerading
as common sense than Christians in other branches of the church or during other historical
periods. These facts make it clear that
constructing
an ethics of
imagination poses formidable
challenges.
What can
help
us address these
challenges
success- fully ?
Not
surprisingly,
the answer here is similar to the earlier one about becoming
communities of
memory. Constructing
an ethics of
imagination requires precisely
the kind of intellectual
discipline,
awareness of issues and alternative
approaches,
and tolerance for
uncertainty
that I have
already associated with a liberally educated mind.
Theologians, ethicists,
and other intellectuals in the church must assume a leading role in the
process
of con- ceptualization.
As
Dempster rightly points out, attending attentively
to the biblical narratives is
indispensable.
But the moral
imagination
can also be sparked by
careful, patient
reflection on the
writings
of
philosophers,
the- ologians,
novelists, and playwrights outside the Pentecostal tradition as well as those of scholars in the social sciences and humanities. This
type
of reflection not
only helps
reveal models that have
already
been
articulated, but also, and perhaps most
importantly,
assists us in discovering and assess- ing our
own moral
assumptions. Finally, although
Pentecostal scholars bear a
special responsibility
to lead the
way,
the
process
must continue in the churches. The
clergy,
who control the
governance
structures in all Pentecostal denominations, must concede the
poverty
of
simple proof-text approaches
to moral
questions. They
must
acknowledge
the need for a com- prehensive
and principled
approach
and must
give
enthusiastic endorsement to the kinds of intellectual efforts
necessary
to undertake such a task, know- ing full
well that no algorithm exists for completing it. Moreover,
they
must endorse the
development
of educational
programs
in the church and in our colleges
and universities that are based not on the dissemination of moral dogma
but on the
development
of moral
reasoning.
Moral
education,
while it cannot and should not exclude
preaching,
must include
teaching
and dis- cussion.
Conclusion
Appropriating
the
past
and
informing
moral consciousness
214
, are two
18
obvious
ways
liberal education offers the
prospect
of making a discernible contribution to Pentecostals at this
point
in their
history. Certainly they
are not the only areas of stewardship that merit attention.
Consider,
for instance, that in many
parts
of the world Pentecostals no longer occupy the
margins of society but find themselves
increasingly
in a position to build and
shape culture. What will they offer? That will depend in no small
part on how crit- ically
and
imaginatively they
are
finally
able to think within a Christian framework across a broad
spectrum
of subjects, from economics to political science and social
theory,
and from the humanities to the empirical sciences. Consider, too,
the new
digital technology,
which not
only presents
remark- able
opportunities
but
poses
certain fundamental
challenges
as well. If past is prologue, Pentecostals will repeat the mistakes
they
made at the beginning of the television
age: criticizing
the content but
failing altogether
to under- stand the
philosophical,
social, and moral
implications
of the device itself. The new
digital technologies, exemplified by
the Internet-connected com- puter,
have the capacity to transform
community
life more
profoundly
than television and to reshape our
understanding
of Scripture
(hypertext
is not the same as printed
text).
How will Pentecostals
respond?
Here
again
the answer has much to do with the
stewardship they
exercise over the educative processes
that
shape
their minds.
The
temptation,
of
course,
is to concede that the
“tongues-talking” woman from
Mississippi,
who wondered whether we could
any longer jus- tify devoting
attention to classical literature like Homer’s
Odyssey,
is right. How can we afford to
spend
time with literature or poetry?-or with works of
history, philosophy, theology,
or
ethics?-or, for
that matter, with the principal
stories and heroes in our own brief Pentecostal tradition? Faced with
urgent
and formidable
problems,
should we not address ourselves sin- gle mindedly
to solving them? These
questions presume
the priority of prob- lems over the
development
of the self who is
expected
to meet the chal- lenges
that such
problems pose. They
also
express
a way of
thinking
that explains why
liberal education
languishes among
Pentecostals, at every level and in point of recognition as their most basic educational need. The fundamental
question facing
Pentecostals however, is not whether
they
will be able to acquire the material or political resources to “solve
problems,”
but whether
they
will prove to be adequately prepared to meet the
responsibili- ties that will
inevitably
be thrust
upon
them in the
twenty-first century.
At bottom,
this is a question about whether
they
will
bring
to problems an his- torical
sensibility,
a deliberate and judicious frame of mind, and the
capaci-
.
215
19
ty to think imaginatively
and
reflectively.
In short, it is a question about the formation and discipline of the mind.35
35 I am indebted to my colleagues Robert Berg and Gary Liddle for reading and offering criti- cal commentary on this essay.
216
20
Leave a Reply